OBSERVARE
Universidade Autónoma de Lisboa
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
THE INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL COURT
REFLECTIONS FOR A STRESS TEST ON ITS FOUNDATIONS
Mateus Kowalski
email: mateus.kowalski@gmail.com
PhD student in International Politics and Conflict Resolution at Universidade de Coimbra, holder
of a Master Degree in International Law and of a Bachelor Degree in Law. Author of articles and
papers on the Theory of International Law, the UN system, human rights, and security issues.
Guest lecturer at Universidade Autónoma de Lisboa, where he is a researcher in the field of
international criminal justice (Observatory for External Relations), and at Universidade Aberta.
Legal adviser to the Ministry of Foreign Affairs of Portugal, in the field of International Law
Abstract
The constitution of the ICC in 2002 represents the ultimate example of the evolution of
international criminal justice. The Court is referred to as a paradigmatic institution of the
universalist concept of International Law, which envisages an enhanced international public
order and which falls within the broader framework of the dominant liberal construct that
currently characterizes both International Law and International Relations. However, the
criticisms of universalism, in particular as regards the impositions of global liberal
institutions and regulatory standards, are also reflected on the ICC. In particular, it has
been met with several essential criticisms, such as its dependence on the Security Council,
suggesting political interference in a criminal court, or the fact that until now only issues
pertaining to Africa have been submitted to the Court, which in turn leads to suspicion about
their selectivity. These are the criticisms that undermine the foundations of the ICC.
At a time when the Court has not yet concluded any trial, and when there is still some
scepticism about the success of its mission, knowing what to expect from the ICC in its task
of crime preventing and retribution and building peace depends largely on the strength of
its theoretical foundations. It is argued that despite the seemingly solid support discourse
rooted in universalism, the answers advanced by this theory are not fully satisfactory due
largely to the structural weaknesses that characterise it. This article seeks to offer food for
thought on the subject and starts by gauging the competence of legal universalism to
support “its” ICC with regard to these issues. It then identifies the aspects that can be
addressed in within a more complex context, such as critical theory, which may contribute
to the development of a discourse that grants the Court greater theoretical sustainability.
Keywords
International Criminal Court; International Law; Universalism; Critical Theory
How to cite this article
Kowalski, Mateus (2011). The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on
its foundations”. JANUS.NET e-journal of International Relations, Vol. 2, No. 2, Autumn
2011. Accessed [online] on date of last view, observare.ual.pt/janus.net/en_vol2_n2_art6
Article received on July 2011 and accepted for publication on October 2011
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
111
THE INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL COURT
REFLECTIONS FOR A STRESS TEST ON ITS FOUNDATIONS
Mateus Kowalski
1. Introduction
The implementation of the idea that any person, wherever he/she may be and
regardless of official status may be liable for crimes relevant to the entire humanity
represents a break with the Westphalian paradigm that presupposes that it is up to
each state to do justice to “his” people. Various international criminal courts have been
created after the Cold War, such as the ad hoc tribunals for the former Yugoslavia and
Rwanda, and a permanent criminal court, the International Criminal Court (hereinafter
“ICC”). Power is no longer a shield of impunity as before. The leaders involved in
conflicts learned to fear international criminal justice as the “sword of Damocles”. On
the other hand, the creation of international criminal courts, in their various forms, has
become a method for consolidating peace in post-conflict situations and a mechanism
of restorative justice.
The constitution of the ICC in 2002 represents the ultimate example of the evolution of
international criminal justice. The Court is referred to as a paradigmatic institution of
the universalist concept of International Law, which envisages an enhanced
international public order and which falls within the broader framework of the dominant
liberal construct that currently characterizes both International Law and International
Relations. As referred by Bogdandy and Dellavalle, «in the global context, the
development of this project for a true international public order and a true international
law is currently largely based on the fate of the International Criminal Law» (2008: 2).
However, the criticisms directed to universalism, namely the imposition of liberal global
institutions and regulatory standards, are also reflected on the ICC. These include, in
particular, its dependence on the Security Council, suggesting political interference in a
criminal court, or the fact that until now only issues pertaining to Africa have been
submitted to the Court, which in turn leads to suspicion about their selectivity. These
criticisms undermine the foundations of the ICC in the context of universalism.
At a time when the Court has not yet concluded any trial, and when there is still some
scepticism about the success of its mission, knowing what to expect from the ICC in its
task of crime preventing and retribution and of building peace depends largely on the
strength of its theoretical foundations. This is the argument of the present study, which
argues that despite the seemingly solid support discourse rooted in universalism, the
answers advanced by this theory are not fully satisfactory due largely to the structural
weaknesses that characterise it. Thus, subjecting the ICC to a stress test with regard to
its theoretical foundations enables us to identify its stress points and, at the same time,
seek other theoretical frameworks that may produce a discourse that holds and
sustains it.
This article seeks to offer food for thought on the subject and starts by gauging the
competence of legal universalism to support “its” ICC with regard to these issues. It
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
112
then attempts to identify the aspects that can be addressed within a more complex
context, such as critical theory, which may grant the Court greater theoretical
sustainability.
2. Universalism and the ICC
Theorizing about the universality of public order, and particularly about the current
debate around its constitutionalization is, at the level of International Law, an example
of modern rationality that characterizes prevailing liberal thought. In turn, the narrative
of liberal peace, whose agenda is part of the ICC, is a universalist concept with a
rational basis (Richmond, 2008). Unlike what happens with conservative concepts of
International Law, the currents of thought that embrace universalism argue that
international public order is possible and advisable, even a logical construct led by
reason (Dellavalle, 2010). These currents share a universal conception of public order
that is underpinned by a fundamental normative core common to international players
and institutions for collective action towards universal goals.
For universalism, International Law must comprehensively regulate international
society in the various dimensions of human action in such a way that is not confined to
the jurisdiction of the state and of its various stakeholders, including individuals.
Achieving this goal requires the cooperation and partial integration among states
(ideally democratic) in a process that is properly framed by international organizations.
The ideals of Kant about a cosmopolitan Law and of a world republic founded on reason
constitute the starting point for the universalist understanding of public order which
dominates today and is markedly present in prevailing liberal doctrine. The subjective
mental process ruled by reason that is characteristic of each individual becomes the
common element that underlies universalism.
The dilution of the power of the state into other political levels beyond it, increasingly
stronger globalization of democracy, development and respect for human rights,
chained to the practice of “good governance”, cause new impulses and complement and
deflate domestic constitutional frameworks. This is how the proposal for global
constitutionalism is presented as an apology of universalism of objective rationality.
Global constitutionalism is perhaps the most important structural change in recent
times in International Law and has impacted profoundly on the debate around the
subject (Machado, 2006). Basically, the proposal for universal constitutionalism offers a
legal compensation to state constitutional shortages brought about by globalization
(Peters, 2009).
The ICC clearly fits this liberal universalist conception, and this is shown in two ways:
on the one hand, in the exercise of criminal justice beyond the State, and on the other,
in the importance given to the individual as a subject relevant to international social
relations.
As regards to the first, criminal prosecution is a power that traditionally forms part of
the core sovereignty of States. The ICC represents a break with this classical postulate:
the power for criminal prosecution is also exercised by a en entity that stands beyond
the public competencies of states. This international criminal prosecution power does
not require authorization by the states. The investigation, arrest warrant and the trial
may be triggered by a decision of the Court and may even oppose the will of the states
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
113
that have primary jurisdiction over it. This is the case when the jurisdiction has been
established by the Prosecutor or by the Security Council under Article 13 of the ICC
Statute, which may even imply the exercise of jurisdiction over states that are not
Party to the Statute. This is reflected in the strengthening of the international public
order, whereby it is granted criminal jurisdiction, similar to what happens in state
orders.
As regards to the second point, it is worth noting that the Court exercises its action
centred on the individual, as it aims, through the exercise of justice, at fulfilling the
objectives of protecting and promoting human rights, restricting the use of force and
reducing its effects on civilians. Under the ICC, these objectives denote a concern about
the universal dignity of human beings, which is a concern of the international
community and not merely of the state. But this centralization on individuals has also
other equally important manifestations, such as the individuals’ capacity to intervene in
international criminal proceedings. However, none of the parties in the process is a
state: rather, on the one side there is the Prosecutor, and on the other the defendant
1
.
Then, the Prosecutor’s investigation may have originated in information given by non-
governmental organizations, which also contribute to the collection of documentary and
testimonial evidence. It is also important to stress that an international employee, the
ICC’s Prosecutor, may, on his own initiative, start an investigation
2
. Finally, the victims
intervene in the process, taking on a role similar to the one assigned to them in
punishments decided by states.
3. Criticism of the ICC and the Response of Universalism
Currently, the ICC has met with hard and lasting criticism with regard its foundations
and which somehow reflects a concern about the decision to impose liberal “Western”
ethical and regulatory solutions. This criticism is basically twofold: statutory and
factual. Regardless of the fact that this criticism may be based on reasons of a juridical
nature or on everyday political motivations, it is possible to identify, from a universalist
perspective, arguments that seek to rebut those criticisms and support the ICC by
means of a discourse anchored on objective rationality.
3.1. Dependence on the Security Council
Criticism that the action of the Court is excessively dependent on the Security Council
and, therefore, largely determined by political rather than legal criteria of its
jurisdiction, is a concern that refers to a statutory aspect. Indeed, the power of the
Security Council over the action of the ICC is stated in the Statute of the Court,
particularly in Articles 13 and 16.
Article 13, clause b) states that the Security Council may refer a situation in which
there is evidence of serious crimes having been committed within the jurisdiction of the
1
The designation of cases brought to the ICC reflects the idea that we are dealing with an international
accusation system where the parties are the Prosecutor and the defendant. For example, the first case of
the ICC is called Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dilo.
2
Article 15 of the Statute of the ICC.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
114
ICC to the Prosecutor. Thus, of the seven cases under consideration
3
, two were
submitted by the former. This power granted to the Security Council has, since the
preparatory work behind the ICC Statute, met with several objections, ranging from the
loss of independence and credibility of the Court, to the argument that the Security
Council has no competence in matters of international criminal justice under the terms
of the United Nations Charter and to the accusation that this creates a situation of
selectivity in the establishment of jurisdiction (Yee, 1999).
The underlying point in any of these criticisms is that cases referred to the ICC are
subject to political decision criteria that are different from the eligibility criteria specific
to a court like the ICC. In addition, there is the fact that of the five permanent
members of the Security Council, three China, the US and Russia are not Party to
the Statute of the Court. Given that they have right to veto
4
, any situation occurring in
their territories or involving their own nationals would certainly never have the chance
of being referred to the Court. This reinforces the idea that the jurisdiction exercise of
the Court may be selective, depending on the dynamics of the Security Council.
The power of the Security Council under Article 16 is, however, the one that has been
touted as the most serious example of political interference. Under its terms, the
Security Council may decide to suspend any investigation or criminal proceedings in
progress at the ICC for a period of twelve months, which is renewable. The Security
Council has gone to the extent of passing resolutions conferring immunity to persons
involved in peacekeeping operations at the service of a state that is not Party to the
ICC Statute.
5
It can even be argued that this is a modification of the Rome Statute by the Security
Council (Jain, 2005). This, on the one hand, conflicts with the objective of fighting
impunity for the gravest international crimes, and, on the other, attests the full extent
of intervention the Security Council is prepared to undertake. Several human rights
non-governmental organizations have indeed pointed to the promiscuity between
judicial action and political logic as being harmful to international criminal justice
(Bourdon, 2000). A mechanism for consultation and dialogue between the Security
Council and the Court would have been favoured instead (Bourdon, 2000).
In cases of crime of aggression, the role of the Security Council extends even further.
The ICC Statute review conference held in Kampala in 2010 introduced the crime of
aggression not initially defined in the Statute and established that the exercise of
jurisdiction by the Court depends on prior decision by the Security Council that there
has indeed been an act of aggression
6
.
In this critical view of the role of the Security Council with regard to the ICC there is an
underlying concern about the duties of an executive entity that is centred on the
narrow circle of its permanent members and with no real mechanisms of political
control or jurisdiction (Kowalski, 2010). This is a concern for which the very discourse
of universalism does not provide an answer.
3
Including the situation on the Ivory Coast, whose admissibility, at the time this paper is being written, is
being considered by the 2
nd
Trial Court.
4
See articles 27, no. 3 of the UN Charter and 13 b) of the Statute of the ICC.
5
See, for instance Resolutions S/RES/1422, of 12 July 2002 and S/RES/1487, of 12 June 2003.
6
See UN Depository Notification C.N.651.2010.TREATIES-8, 29 November 2010. The Court may exercise
its jurisdiction if the Security Council does not act within six months after being notified by the
Prosecutor of his intention to open an investigation into an act of aggression.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
115
Nevertheless, the analysis of the issue from the perspective of universalism produces
arguments that relegate those criticisms to secondary place, stressing instead the
evolution in shaping the international order. Accordingly, in what concerns the capacity
of the Security Council to submit a situation to the Court, it means, therefore, that the
ICC has the possibility of prosecuting crimes connected to states which are not Party to
the Statute and over which it could not otherwise exercise its jurisdiction. More than
anything, the intervention of the Security Council under Article 13 clause b) is a
mechanism that allows circumventing the wills of States and thus extend the
jurisdiction of the Court. Given that only 116 States are Party to the Statute, the
mechanism for the Security Council’s submission potentially guarantees that the Court
may try crimes committed anywhere by anyone. On the other hand, the Security
Council effectively has authority to deal with matters of a criminal nature, which was
actually the argument advanced by the ICC with regard to the Former Yugoslavia on
the Tadić case
7
. Another argument in favour of this option is that the Security Council
would cease to establish ad hoc criminal courts, as in the case of the former Yugoslavia
and Rwanda (Cassese, 2008).
With regard to the more controversial power of suspension of investigation or criminal
proceedings in progress, the universalism discourse will defend that this was a
necessary negotiation compromise mechanism: there should be a balance between the
action of the Court and the primary responsibility of the Security Council in maintaining
peace and international security. Moreover, the analysis of the preparatory work shows
that Article 16 strips powers from the Security Council in relation to the draft Statute
prepared by the International Law Commission and which formed the basis for
negotiations.
8
The at time Article 23, point 3 of that draft provided that the ICC could
not initiate any proceedings with regard to a matter under discussion at the Security
Council pursuant to chapter VII of the Charter, unless the latter decided otherwise.
After intense negotiations in what became known as the “compromise of Singapore”,
the way the Security Council intervened was inverted, with the latter acting only when
it wishes to suspend the procedure.
On the other hand, it is a fact that, so far, the Security Council has never resorted to its
power to suspend an investigation or criminal proceeding in progress. Some African
States have even exerted great pressure on the Security Council to exercise the power
conferred to it under Article 16 of the ICC Statute, namely with regard to the situation
in Sudan (Darfur) where Omar Al Bashir, President of Sudan, is charged with genocide,
crimes against humanity and war crimes. This attests the responsibility and caution
with which the Security Council exercises this power.
Thus, according to this concept and when those dispositions are analysed in the
broader context of international criminal prosecution, the intervention of the Security
Council is the result of a consensus necessary to build the ICC, and means a relative
evil, even a possible benefit. Following this line of reasoning, and despite the abundant
literature that advances arguments such as the vulnerability of nationals from the
United States or even the absence of trial before a jury because that State is not Party
7
Prosecutor v. Duško Tadić, ICTY Appeals Chamber, Decision on the Defence Motion for Interlocutory
Appeal on Jurisdiction, 2 October 1995.
8
See International Law Commission (1997). Yearbook of the International Law Commission: 1994, II(2).
New York: United Nations.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
116
to the Statute, Schabas defends that the rub lies actually on the excessive
independence of the ICC with regard to the Security Council (2004).
3.2. Selectivity in the exercise of Jurisdiction
Another strong criticism that has been advanced mainly at political and diplomatic
levels and that has generated some hostility by African States with regard to the ICC
has to do with a factual point: so far only situations concerning Africa have been
submitted to the ICC. This would illustrate the selectivity of the Court.
All seven cases referred to the ICC pertain only to African States: Uganda, the
Democratic Republic of the Congo, Central African Republic, Sudan (Darfur), Kenya,
Libya, and the Ivory Coast. This factual and undeniable finding has fostered the
accusation that the ICC is not impartial in the establishment of its jurisdiction, and this
has been coupled by complaints, at least implicit, of neo-colonialism.
The accusations have gathered the protest of several States in Africa, more or less
united in a common stance, which has manifested itself primarily through the African
Union. Following the ICC arrest warrant against Omar Al Bashir, there has been a harsh
reaction against the Court’s attempt to bring African leaders to trial, particularly from
States that are not Party to the ICC Statute. At the 15
th
Summit of the African Union,
its Member States have confirmed that they would not cooperate with the Court in the
arrest and submission of Omar Al Bashir. On the other hand, they refused a closer
cooperation with the ICC by turning down the opening of a liaison office in Adis Abeba
9
.
The travels of the President of Sudan to countries that are Party to the Statute of the
Court have also generated some tension. In Omar Al Bashir’s controversial trip to Chad
and Kenya, the ICC demanded that those States complied with the arrest warrant and
handed in the President of Sudan to the Court. The African Union responded in a
serious manner advancing decisions taken by that organization and arguing that it
knew the reality of the region better
10
, thus assuming an attitude of rejection against
neo-colonialist interference. More recently, the issuance of an arrest warrant by the ICC
against Libyan leader Muammar Gaddafi took the African Union to ask its members to
ignore such warrant. As if summarizing the concerns of several African States, the
President of the African Union Commission, Jean Ping, stated that the ICC is
discriminatory because it only deals with crimes committed in Africa, ignoring those
carried out by “Western powers” in Iraq, Afghanistan and Pakistan.
11
In this sense, the African Union has repeatedly tried that the Security Council of the
United Nations suspends the proceedings in progress at the ICC against Al Bashir
12
by
resorting to the dispositions in Article 16 of the ICC’s Statute. As the Security Council
has not shown any openness to suspend the proceedings, the African Union went to the
extent of proposing an amendment to Article 16 requesting that when the Security
9
See “15th AU Summit – Press Release 104: ‘Decisions on the 15th AU Summit’”, 29 July 2010.
10
See “AU Press Release 118/2010”, 29 August 2010.
11
See Associated Press “African Union calls on Member States to Disregard ICC Arrest Warrant Against
Libya’s Gadhafi”, 2 July 2011.
12
See “AU Press Release 118/2010”, 29 August 2010.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
117
Council refuses to act, its authority be transferred to the UN General Assembly
13
, where
the suspension of a case would have more favourable conditions for approval.
The reasons for this type of criticism are essentially political, to which the discourse
rooted in universalism responds with strict observance of the ICC Statute criteria, in
which thirty two African States are present, making it the largest group represented.
Thus, it immediately points out that complementary is a principle that informs the ICC’s
exercise of jurisdiction. Under the terms of Article 1 of the Statute, it means that the
ICC is complementary to national jurisdictions on criminal matters, exercising it only
when the latter do not want or are not genuinely able to do so. Not to be able to
enforce jurisdiction, which may require the further intervention of the ICC, includes
those cases in which suspects have been covered by an amnesty (Cassese, 2008). This
subsidiary position in relation to national jurisdictions is also intended to encourage
States to start criminal proceedings when crimes of extreme gravity are involved
(Kleffner, 2008). This complementary principle opposes the primacy enjoyed by the ad
hoc tribunals set up for the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda with regard to the
corresponding national criminal jurisdictions.
Therefore, when the ICC started criminal proceedings in those situations in African
States, it did so because either the states themselves denounced the situation which
is what happens in most cases
14
or because there was strong evidence of serious
crimes that were relevant for the entire international community and the States with
primary jurisdiction did not want or were genuinely unable to conduct the trial. The fact
that the Court is analysing situations of States that are not Party to the Statute - such
as Sudan or Libya cannot be subject to criticism, inasmuch as that possibility is
inherent to the very same Statute and aims to avoid situations of impunity.
That said, the accusation of selectivity would only make sense if arguments were
advanced for other situations in the world to be referred to the Court. In this case, it
would not be the correctness of the cases under consideration relating to situations in
Africa, but the injustice of other cases remaining unpunished. In addition, the fact
remains that other situations have been or are still being considered by the Court,
particularly by the Office of the Prosecutor, and which include other regions besides
Africa, namely facts that took place in Afghanistan, Colombia, Georgia, Guinea, Iraq,
Palestine, Venezuela, Nigeria, Honduras, and in the Republic of Korea. The preliminary
assessment is subject to general and abstract criteria established by the Prosecutor
based on the Statute of the Court
15
, which formally prevents any selectivity or
discrimination in the decision to start, or not, criminal proceedings in a given situation.
4. The shortcomings of Universalism: Are there Alternatives?
The two sets of criticism referred to earlier deserve a seemingly secure and convincing
answer on the part of the universalism discourse, and one that is formulated around
logical-deductive arguments and that attests the sustainability of the Court as a
structural component of the international public order. However, if one shifts the focus
13
See “Report on the Ministerial Meeting on the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC)”,
AU Executive Council Document EX.CL/568 (XVI), 29 January 2010.
14
These are the cases of Uganda, the Democratic Republic of Congo, the Central African Republic or the
Ivory Coast.
15
See “Draft Policy Paper on Preliminary Examinations”, 4 October 2010, www.icc-cpi.int.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
118
of criticism to the actual universalist construct, then it will be the theoretical framework
of international public order in which the Court is set which will be called into question.
The ICC may find itself devoid of a theoretical support and at the risk of breakdown or
at least of being relegated to a secondary role in the international system when its
state of grace comes to an end.
The criticism, gaps and unmet needs of the universalist theory, particularly in the field
of global constitutionalism, lead to the need to probe new avenues for International
Law as a juridical science. The post-positivist approach, namely that rooted in critical
theory, which is more advanced in other social sciences, including International
Relations, may offer a way to rethink International Law. Particularly with regard to the
ICC, it is important to identify some key aspect of the Court that enables its
interpretation and justification beyond the shortcomings of universalism.
4.1. The shortcomings of Universalism
Any attempt do define international public order solely in terms of universalism,
particularly global constitutionalism, by looking at the state is an exercise that risks
being a failed promise for International Law and for the international social systems it
envisages to regulate, because one cannot draw a parallel between the concerns and
response mechanisms of both (Uruena, 2009). In the description of Koskenniemi,
global constitutionalism is intuitively interpreted as if it was domestic constitutionalism:
«multilateral treaties as legislation; international tribunals as independent jurisdictional
powers; the Security Council as the police» (2005a: 117).
The lure of the global constitutionalism project must be restrained by an alert critical
exercise. Firstly because in the current framework of international social relations, the
project risks enhancing the dynamic of power rationales which already influence the
more or less institutionalised, and more or less informal, international social relations.
For this reason, Zolo draws attention to the dangers of global constitutionalism centred
on the United Nations Charter which can lead to excessive concentration of power,
making «the international protection of rights and the pursuit of peace even more
precarious» (1997: 121). Despite the dominance of liberalism, which is indeed
detached from simplified power relations, the fact is that international social relations
are still dominated by a state-centred rationale that aims to influence global
governance according to own interests, thus forming a “hegemonic bloc”.
The structuring power of liberalism finds a correspondence in current International Law
(Koskenniemi, 2005b). The theory of International Law has, indeed, taken the Law (or
the rule) and power (or political reality) as the two axes of reference. This double
dimension of International Law immediately turned it into a tool for the States, and
increasingly a key factor for shaping international society. This means a concern to
ensure the balance between Law and power, between legitimation and resistance
(Krisch, 2005): on the one hand, to ensure a distance between law and political reality
that hampers the political defence and absolute freedom of the State; on the other, the
approximation of Law to the political reality to avoid the utopia of mismatched social
solutions (Koskenniemi, 2005b).
The liberal agenda and manifestations are clearly also infiltrated, albeit in a more
subliminal form due to the fact that the international structure is more complex by
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
119
power rationales. In the framework of the universalist concept, liberalism provides a
theoretical cover that confers it a scientific rationale that legitimizes the pursuit of
individual interests by the States which greater capacity to do so i.e. those with
greater power. The “problem solution” approach that characterises liberalism and
currently predominates in the theory and practice of International Law can serve a
domination strategy. Accordingly, by acting as if the structures actually reflect a
particular set of true and unique ideas, the problems that affect the functioning norms,
processes and institutions get solved, and structures are deemed to be immovable. This
leads to the stabilization of those norms, processes and institutions, as well as to the
crystallization of structures that may lie at the root of the problem, without an
alternative being sought. Thus, power and truth feed each other (Foucault, 1980).
However, this methodological and somewhat ideological understanding is rooted on a
wrong premise: that political and social reality is immutable (Cox, 1981). Critique of
this liberal approach encourages, as stated by Cox, «a strategic action guideline to
bring about an alternative order» (1981: 130).
4.2. Post-Positivism in International Law
For some post-positivist stances, universalism is possible and eventually desirable.
However, from the epistemological viewpoint, it moves away from the notion of a
universal rationality that enables the universal objectivation of reality. Critical theory
challenges the central possibility of objective knowledge, that societies and individuals
are part of a natural order or that knowledge can only be acquired through experience
(Hollis, 1996). Accordingly, it states that the object of perception (empirical reality), be
it in the context of legal, social, political, economic or cultural relations, is inseparable
from the subject that is trying to capture it, analyze it and explain it.
Critical theory, faced with the shortcomings of single truth departing ideas, as well as of
orthodox universalist ontology and epistemology, aims to overcome them by resorting
to the central concept of emancipation. The ethical discourse leads to greater freedom
and emancipation detached from the Westphalian straitjacket which never really allows
seeing beyond the State. The post-positivist critical theory alternative is thus able to
withstand the rational basis of universalism as a form of hegemony by granting it
increased representativeness (Hoffman, 1988). Knowledge, discourse, equal
opportunities or justice are ethical elements that act as a shield against hegemony.
Post-positivism thought fosters a multidisciplinary interpretation of international social
relations, particularly at the level of International Relations and International Law. The
impulse given by critical theory applied to Political Science, particularly with regard to
International Relations, feeds from other social sciences where social critical theory is
more advanced and more present in specific ideas (George, 1994). This is perhaps one
of the most important advances in contemporary theory of International Relations
(Richmond, 2008): the abandonment of the defence of the eternal present and the
quest for a richer theory (Pureza, 1999).
In terms of International law, the critical process that underlies the post-positivist
approach has moved in two major opposing trends: on the one hand, there is a current
that calls for a theoretical redefinition without cutting completely with the existing
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
120
system this current is influenced by the Frankfurt School
16
; on the other, stands the
trend that advocates a total break with modernity as it would prove impossible to use
any of its bases for the necessary new theory
17
. Without wishing to expand on this, as
this is not the place, it is, nevertheless, important to demystify the idea that critical
theory necessarily implies condemning International Law (Carty, 1991) and that
deconstruction means destruction.
A post-positivist analysis allows us to say that International Law can be different from
the one built by the theory and practice of orthodox liberalism, and certainly of
liberalism. This can give rise to a new conception of International Law based on a post-
positivist paradigm: stress the critical theory dimension in International Law and thus
build a true ethical and normative system and a legitimizing authoritative discourse
which conforms to an international society that is less oligarchic and more equal
(Pureza, 1998).
The ontology of this International Law is not just objective or empirical” reality, but
also its subjective representation, with a normative base and a transformative
intention, in which everyday life and empathy are operational concepts. An
International Law that aims to be a factor for transformation cannot simply break with
political reality and pretend it never existed. First it needs to understand this reality in
order to deconstruct it and then attempt a critique towards the construction of an
alternative system. For this reason, and although there is a break with the theoretical
postulates of the orthodox notions of International Law, critique cannot ignore objective
reality (norms, facts, institutions, processes) upon which it wants to act.
4.3. Elements for an interpretation of the ICC in a Post-Positivist
Framework
Post-positivist thought, especially in the context of critical theory, can lead to a divisive
deconstruction of current international organizations, particularly if interpreted as an
attempt to break with post-modernism: Koskenniemi argues in favour of International
Law as an alternative to the current international order, saying this could be achieved
through the empowerment of independent groups outside international organizations
(2004); Kennedy, in turn, defends that the ICC was a “bad idea” (Moore, 2005).
Without wishing to start a debate about post-modernism in this paper, it must be
pointed out that there are some aspects about the Court that should be reflected upon
and interpreted in a post-positivist approach, particularly in the context of critical
theory.
Both sets of criticisms referred to earlier, currently quite audible, could be, and they
are, to some extent, fed by the discourse of critical theory. However, there are aspects
that are core to the ICC that could be the starting point to inform a post-positivist
16
See, among others: Habermas, Jürgen (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1: Reason and
the Rationalization of Society. Boston: Beacon Press; Habermas, Jürgen (1987). The Theory of
Communicative Action, vol. 2: Lifeworld and System – a Critique of Functionalist Reason. Boston: Beacon
Press; Habermas, Jürgen (2008). «A Political Constitution for the Pluralist World Society?». In Jürgen
Habermas (ed.), Between Naturalism and Religion. Cambridge: Polity Press, 312-352.
17
See, among others: Koskenniemi, Martti (2005). From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International
Legal Argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Kennedy, David (2004). «Speaking Law to
Power: International Law and Foreign Policy Closing Remarks». Wisconsin International Law Journal.
23(1), 173-181.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
121
construct that holds the Court in a discourse of emancipation and transformation
anchored on ideals rooted on human dignity. The figure of the Prosecutor and the role
of civil society are examples of such elements, which are mentioned here as a
suggestion for future reflection.
The Prosecutor, that it, the Office for the Prosecutor
18
, is responsible for receiving
information on crimes within the jurisdiction of the Court, examine them, carry out
investigation and institute criminal proceedings before the Court. The Prosecutor is
autonomous with regard to the Court and can start an investigation and charge
individuals for the practice of crimes under the jurisdiction of the ICC, always subject,
of course, to further examination by the competent Court. In what concerns crimes
committed in the territory or by a State Party to the Statute, the Prosecutor exercises
those powers motu proprio. This, incidentally, is considered to be one of the important
achievements for human rights non-governmental organizations and for the victims
(Bourdon, 2000).
The figure of the Prosecutor of the ICC has no parallel in the international system. It is
an international official who exercises criminal jurisdiction independently, and he can
investigate, charge and order the arrest of individuals of any nationality, regardless of
their official position or even the will of States. The status of the Prosecutor and his
authority are a break with the Westphalian order. On the other hand, the independent
exercise of his powers contributes to the development of the international social system
by means of international ethical and normative postulates centred on human dignity.
In turn, both organizations and individuals from civil society have left a decisive mark
on the Court, basically due to three aspects: the establishment of the ICC, collaboration
in the investigations and collection of evidence, and in promoting the role of the Court
and the universality purpose of its Statute. The first two aspects deserve special
mention.
The contribution of civil society in the creation of the Court and even in the framing of
the Statute is a landmark in the formation of International Law and in the constitution
of international organizations (Glasius, 2006). It is significant that two hundred and
thirty seven non-governmental organizations from around the world were accredited at
the diplomatic conference that adopted the ICC Statute in Rome on 17 July 1998.
19
These organizations had direct influence on the drafting of some of the provisions of
the Statute through collaborative work (Struett, 2008).
The intervention of non-governmental organizations in reporting crimes under the ICC’s
jurisdiction
20
and in the investigation of cases is another aspect that attests the
importance of civil society in the functioning of the Court. Non-governmental
organizations have always had very close contact with serious human rights violations,
documenting and reporting them. The close contact with victims and witnesses has
been of paramount importance for their protection and collection of evidence. Their
contribution in terms of reporting situations and investigating cases can thus be
decisive (HRF, 2004). It should be noted that the attribution of a role to non-
governmental organizations pursuant to Article 15 no. 2 of the Statute is a landmark in
18
In accordance with Article 42 of the Statute of the ICC, the Prosecutor chairs the entity “Office of the
Prosecutor”.
19
See UN Document A/CONF.183/INF/3, 5 June 1998.
20
By May 2011 the Office of the Prosecutor had received around 4,898 communications with some sort of
connection to the jurisdiction of the Court. Source: ICC – www.icc-cpi.int.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
122
the international institutionalization of civil society. It is equally relevant that the
information conveyed by NGOs is handled by the Office of the Prosecutor, who is
responsible, at least initially, to determine its importance in the context of an
investigation or prosecution.
These two elements for reflection could be joined by a third pertaining to the contents
of the principle of complementarity of the ICC’s jurisdiction. It concerns the
development of this principle by seeking local forms, including traditional ones, of
administering justice. Indeed, there is a recent trend to soften the dialogue between
peace versus justice in the context of the Court and the subsequent focus on finding
new forms of justice of proximity that are complementary to the ICC (Ambos et al.,
2009).
5. Conclusion
The creation of the ICC should be seen not only as an innovation but above all as an
achievement of civilization in the defence of human dignity and in the promotion of
peace. The long journey undertaken so far has also contributed to a paradigm shift in
International Law and International Relations, whose focus is moving away from States
and refocusing on the individuals. Nevertheless, this is a long way that we are still
taking.
Almost ten years after the creation of the Court, the results that is, to put it bluntly,
the convictions are still lacking, contributing to the swell of criticism and to feed a
sceptical discourse which, until some time ago, had been overwhelmed by the
excessive enthusiasm surrounding the Court at academic, diplomatic and political level,
which was also shared by the civil society. The structural criticism that it receives,
namely its dependence on an oligarchic organ of realism which represents an expired
order the Security Council and its selective action which, to date, has only targeted
African States, undermine its foundations.
The accusation behind these criticisms is the global imposition of liberal ethical and
normative standards. Even if the selectivity criticism is inspired more by a state-based
particularistic stance rather than by a universalist perspective, the truth is that it is the
international public order viewed from an universalist stance that is being questioned.
The responses of universalism are effective, but they stand the stress tests only
because universalism itself is insufficient.
The ICC is still living in a state of grace. However, the risk of marginalization has been
increasing. The review conference in Kampala in 2010 was a warning: the sun had not
yet set over Lake Victoria on the last day of the conference and there were already
differences about the application of what had been agreed. Indeed, to date no State
has bound to the amendments adopted at the conference, including those relating to
the definition of the crime of aggression.
Reflection on the ideals behind the ICC must be ongoing in order to create an ethical
legitimation discourse that grants it effective resilience and transformation capacity.
But in order to have legitimacy, it is necessary to ensure critique, deconstruction and
disclosure so that the hopes placed on the ICC may be linked to the hope in the critical
reflection and in the will of all the international players involved in it.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
123
The considerations presented in this paper are proposals that seek to contribute to a
reflection on the theoretical sustainability of the ICC in the current liberal universalist
framework. Consequently, accepting that the ICC may be developed according to a
post-positivist stance, and not simply marginalized, is important not only to the Court
itself but also to the development of an International Law theory which, alongside
International Relations, gets the impact of the shortcomings of liberalism-based legal
universalism and is able to offer a viable, emancipatory and transformative alternative.
Ascertaining if that is actually possible may require a contextualized analysis based on
the reflection proposed here.
Bibliography
Ambos, Kai et al. (eds.) (2009). Building a Future on Peace and Justice: Studies on
Transitional Justice, Conflict Resolution and Development the Nuremberg Declaration
on Peace and Justice. Berlin: Springer.
Bogdandy, Armin; Dellavalle, Sergio (2008). “Universalism and Particularism as
Paradigms of International Law”. In IILJ Working Paper 2008/3 [online]. [Accessed on 2
June 2011]. Available at www.iilj.org/publications/documents/2008-3.Bogdandy-
Dellavalle.pdf.
Bourdon, William (2000). La Cour Pénale Internationale: Le Statut de Rome. Paris:
Éditions du Seuil.
Carty, Anthony (1991). “Critical International Law: Recent Trends in the Theory of
International Law”. European Journal of International Law. 2(1): 1-27.
Cassese, Antonio (2008). International Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cox, Robert (1981). “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International
Relations Theory”. Millennium – Journal of International Affairs. 10(2): 126-155.
Dellavalle, Sergio (2010). “Beyond Particularism: Remarks on Some Recent Approaches
to the Idea of a Universal Political and Legal Order”. European Journal of International
Law. 21(3): 765-788.
Foucault, Michel (1980). Power / Knowledge: Selected Interviews and other Writings,
1972-1977. Brighton: The Harvester Press.
George, Jim (1994). Discourses of Global Politics. Boulder: Lynne Rienner.
Glasius, Marlies (2006). The International Criminal Court: A Global Civil Society
Achievement. Oxon: Routledge.
Hoffman, Mark (1988). “Conversations on Critical Theory”. Millennium Journal of
International Studies. 17(1): 91-95.
Hollis, Martin (1996). “The Last Post”. In Steve Smith et al. (ed.), International Theory:
Positivism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 301-308.
HRF: Human Rights First (2004). “The Role of Human Rights NGOs in Relation to ICC
Investigations”. In Human Rights First [online]. [Accessed on 4 June 2011]. Available
at
www.amicc.org/docs/Human%20Rights%20First%20NGO_Role_Discussion_Paper.pdf.
JANUS.NET, e-journal of International Relations
ISSN: 1647-7251
Vol. 2, no. 2 (Autumn 2011), pp. 110-124
The International Criminal Court. Reflections for a stress test on its foundations
Mateus Kowalski
124
Jain, Neha (2005). “A Separate Law for Peacekeepers: The Clash Between the Security
Council and the International Criminal Court”. European Journal of International Law.
16(2): 239-254.
Kleffner, Jann (2008). Complementarity in the Rome Statute and National Criminal
Jurisdictions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Koskenniemi, Martti (2004). “Global Governance and Public International Law”.
Kritische Justiz. 37: 241-254.
Koskenniemi, Martti (2005a). “International Law in Europe: Between Tradition and
Renewal”. European Journal of International Law. 16(1): 113-124.
Koskenniemi, Martti (2005b). From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International
Legal Argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kowalski, Mateus (2010). “O Conselho de Segurança das Nações Unidas: o Grande
Leviatã?”. Negócios Estrangeiros. 18: 159-184.
Krisch, Nico (2005). “International Law in Times of Hegemony: Unequal Power and the
Shaping of the International Legal Order”. European Journal of International Law.
16(3): 369-408.
Machado, Jónatas (2006). Direito Internacional: Do Paradigma Clássico ao Pós-11 de
Setembro. Coimbra: Coimbra Editora.
Moore, Iván (2005). “Entrevista a David Kennedy: La Corte Penal Internacional Fue
Una Mala Idea”. Themis – Revista de Derecho. 50: 329-335.
Peters, Anne (2009). “The Merits of Global Constitutionalism”. Indiana Journal of Global
Legal Studies. 16(2): 397-411.
Pureza, Jo Manuel (1998). “O Lugar do Direito num Horizonte Pós-Positivista”.
Política Internacional. 2(18): 79-91.
Pureza, José Manuel (1999). “O Príncipe e o Pobre: o Estudo das Relações
Internacionais entre a Tradição e a Reinvenção”. Revista Crítica de Ciências Sociais.
52/53: 363-376.
Richmond, Oliver (2008). Peace in International Relations. Oxon: Routledge.
Schabas, William (2004). “United States Hostility to the International Criminal Court:
It’s All about the Security Council”. European Journal of International Law. 15(4): 701-
720.
Struett, Michael (2008). The Politics of Constructing the International Criminal Court:
NGOs, Discourse and Agency. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Uruena, Rene (2009). “Espejismos Constitucionales: La Promessa Incumplida del
Constitucionalismo Global”. Revista de Derecho Publico. 24: 3-23.
Yee, Lionel (1999). “The International Criminal Court and the Security Council: Articles
13(b) and 16”. In Roy Lee (ed.), The International Criminal Court: The Making of the
Rome Statute. The Hague: Kluwer Law International, 143-152.
Zolo, Danilo (1997). Cosmopolis: Prospects for World Government. Cambridge: Polity
Press.